Apply deontology to ethical dilemma in business

The most familiar forms of deontology, and also the forms presenting the greatest contrast to consequentialism, hold that some choices cannot be justified by their effects—that no matter how morally good their consequences, some choices are morally forbidden.

Presumably, a deontologist can be a moral realist of either the natural moral properties are identical to natural properties or nonnatural moral properties are not themselves natural properties even if they are nonreductively related to natural properties variety.

It disallows consequentialist justifications whenever: This means that an action or practice is ethically correct when it produces more positive consequences in comparison to negative ones to those who are involved. Taurek's argument can be employed to deny the existence of moral catastrophes and thus the worry about them that deontologists would otherwise have.

What was it like on the inside. Oxford Dictionary of English. If deontological norms are so broad in content as to cover all these foreseeings, omittings, and allowings, then good consequences such as a net saving of innocent lives are ineligible to justify them.

Accounts Payable Clerk Consider an accounts payable clerk. A less mysterious way of combining deontology with consequentialism is to assign to each a jurisdiction that is exclusive of the other. In the time-honored example of the run-away trolley Trolleyone may turn a trolley so that it runs over one trapped workman so as to save five workmen trapped on the other track, even though it is not permissible for an agent to have initiated the movement of the trolley towards the one to save five Foot ; Thomson Are dignity and respect for others maintained.

Yet so construed, metaethical contractualism as a method for deriving moral norms does not necessarily lead to deontology as a first order ethics. This person is responsible for reviewing invoices and expense reports, ensuring that they conform to policy and then issuing prompt payment.

In this case, our agency is involved only to the extent that we have shown ourselves as being willing to tolerate evil results flowing from our acts; but we have not set out to achieve such evil by our acts.

A wrong to Y and a wrong to Z cannot be added to make some greater wrong because there is no person who suffers this greater wrong cf. Which is why many naturalists, if they are moral realists in their meta-ethics, are consequentialists in their ethics.

Stevens and Sons, 2nd edition, p. The workers would be saved whether or not he is present on the second track.

Such a view can concede that all human actions must originate with some kind of mental state, often styled a volition or a willing; such a view can even concede that volitions or willings are an intention of a certain kind MooreCh. On the patient-centered version, if an act is otherwise morally justifiable by virtue of its balance of good and bad consequences, and the good consequences are achieved without the necessity of using anyone's body, labor, or talents without that person's consent as the means by which they are achieved, then it is morally immaterial to the permissibility of the act but not to the culpability of the actor whether someone undertakes that act with the intention to achieve its bad consequences.

The greater the wrong, the greater the punishment deserved; and relative stringency of duty violated or importance of rights seems the best way of making sense of greater versus lesser wrongs. On such familiar deontological accounts of morality, agents cannot make certain wrongful choices even if by doing so the number of those exact kinds of wrongful choices will be minimized because other agents will be prevented from engaging in similar wrongful choices.

Law and Morality in an Asymmetrical World, C. The clerk acts in this manner because he believes he has a duty to follow the full and literal policy that the employer had imposed, irrespective of whether the need for originals instead of copies made any difference.

Essays in Political Philosophy, Cambridge: That is, the deontologist might reject the comparability of states of affairs that involve violations and those that do not. Apart from that, they also have to be on the pager 24 hours a day and they are expected to travel around the globe in a short period notice so that, they can catch the next big story.

So, an individual should be able to take a moral action without much dilemma if the decision is right and govern to a set of rules that can be universalized Case, Consequences—and only consequences—can conceivably justify any kind of act, for it does not matter how harmful it is to some so long as it is more beneficial to others.

Patient-centered deontologists handle differently other stock examples of the agent-centered deontologist. Such a core right is not to be confused with more discrete rights, such as the right against being killed, or being killed intentionally. There is an aura of paradox in asserting that all deontological duties are categorical—to be done no matter the consequences—and yet asserting that some of such duties are more stringent than others.

Why is the threshold for torture of the innocent at one thousand lives, say, as opposed to nine hundred or two thousand. After all, the victim of a rights-violating using may suffer less harm than others might have suffered had his rights not been violated; yet one cannot, without begging the question against deontological constraints, argue that therefore no constraint should block minimizing harm.

This makes for a wildly counterintuitive deontology: An illustrative version posits, as its core right, the right against being used only as means for producing good consequences without one's consent. It seemingly justifies each of us keeping our own moral house in order even at the expense of the world becoming much worse.

There are also agent-centered theories that emphasize both intentions and actions equally in constituting the morally relevant agency of persons.  Applying Ethics in an Ethical Dilemma Sean Harrell Walden University Abstract I would never have thought that the hardest part of this assignment was to find a good example of a business organization behaving ethically in an ethical dilemma.

The word deontology derives from the Greek words for duty (deon) and science (or study) of (logos).In contemporary moral philosophy, deontology is one of those kinds of normative theories regarding which choices are morally required, forbidden, or permitted.

How to apply Deontology ethical theory in decision making?

According to the book, Moral Issues in Business, ethical theories can be divided into two classifications: consequential theories (the formal term for these is teleological theories) and non-consequential theories (formal name is deontological theories).

Resolving an Ethical Dilemma Thomas I. White, Ph.D. / [email protected] But in ethical dilemmas that arise in business, the laws generally establish at least a bare minimum for how you should act.

Deontological Ethics

Besides, if a business regularly breaks ethics, the latter, deontological. 2. Teleological (results oriented) ethics. In general, a duty-based ethic -- called deontology by philosophers -- focuses on the act and not its consequence. What Are the Major Ethical Issues Business People Face?

Apply. Apply Deontology To Ethical Dilemma In Business. Solving Ethical Dilemmas in the Accounting Profession LaKeesha Lawler ACC/ January 14, Dan Jensen Solving Ethical Dilemmas in the Accounting Profession The Dilemma of an Accountant Baker Greenleaf was one of the Big Eight accounting firms.

Daniel Potter was a highly ethical accountant that placed a lot of value on integrity.

Apply deontology to ethical dilemma in business
Rated 4/5 based on 48 review
Deontological Ethics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)